英语论文网

留学生硕士论文 英国论文 日语论文 澳洲论文 Turnitin剽窃检测 英语论文发表 留学中国 欧美文学特区 论文寄售中心 论文翻译中心 我要定制

Bussiness ManagementMBAstrategyHuman ResourceMarketingHospitalityE-commerceInternational Tradingproject managementmedia managementLogisticsFinanceAccountingadvertisingLawBusiness LawEducationEconomicsBusiness Reportbusiness planresearch proposal

英语论文题目英语教学英语论文商务英语英语论文格式商务英语翻译广告英语商务英语商务英语教学英语翻译论文英美文学英语语言学文化交流中西方文化差异英语论文范文英语论文开题报告初中英语教学英语论文文献综述英语论文参考文献

ResumeRecommendation LetterMotivation LetterPSapplication letterMBA essayBusiness Letteradmission letter Offer letter

澳大利亚论文英国论文加拿大论文芬兰论文瑞典论文澳洲论文新西兰论文法国论文香港论文挪威论文美国论文泰国论文马来西亚论文台湾论文新加坡论文荷兰论文南非论文西班牙论文爱尔兰论文

小学英语教学初中英语教学英语语法高中英语教学大学英语教学听力口语英语阅读英语词汇学英语素质教育英语教育毕业英语教学法

英语论文开题报告英语毕业论文写作指导英语论文写作笔记handbook英语论文提纲英语论文参考文献英语论文文献综述Research Proposal代写留学论文代写留学作业代写Essay论文英语摘要英语论文任务书英语论文格式专业名词turnitin抄袭检查

temcet听力雅思考试托福考试GMATGRE职称英语理工卫生职称英语综合职称英语职称英语

经贸英语论文题目旅游英语论文题目大学英语论文题目中学英语论文题目小学英语论文题目英语文学论文题目英语教学论文题目英语语言学论文题目委婉语论文题目商务英语论文题目最新英语论文题目英语翻译论文题目英语跨文化论文题目

日本文学日本语言学商务日语日本历史日本经济怎样写日语论文日语论文写作格式日语教学日本社会文化日语开题报告日语论文选题

职称英语理工完形填空历年试题模拟试题补全短文概括大意词汇指导阅读理解例题习题卫生职称英语词汇指导完形填空概括大意历年试题阅读理解补全短文模拟试题例题习题综合职称英语完形填空历年试题模拟试题例题习题词汇指导阅读理解补全短文概括大意

商务英语翻译论文广告英语商务英语商务英语教学

无忧论文网

联系方式

HUMR71-110 EPISTEMOLOGY AND THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE [23]

论文作者:佚名论文属性:短文 essay登出时间:2009-09-22编辑:steelbeezxp点击率:85212

论文字数:36000论文编号:org200909222222328586语种:英语 English地区:英国价格:免费论文

附件:20090922222232113.pdf

关键词:HUMREPISTEMOLOGYTHEORYKNOWLEDGE

could be forgiven at this point for thinking that, unless you are doing advanced work in logic or mathematics, you will only ever be concerned with inductive reasoning, or inductive arguments. However in truth you will probably be involved in a mix.

Consider the following argument:

(Argument 6)

This thin copper wire conducts electricity.
This thick copper wire conducts electricity.
This copper rod conducts electricity.
(Hypothesis) Copper conducts electricity.
So:
(Prediction) A copper surface will conduct electricity.

This is actually a deductive argument. The hypothesis (added as the fourth premise from the top) has been reached inductively. The predictive conclusion follows logically from the premise set.

This is widely believed to be typical of the way much science (including the social sciences) actually works. The prediction is a way of testing the hypothesis. If it turns out false we must do one of two things: either reject the hypothesis (which can be by rejecting it outright or by incorporating a qualification, thereby modifying it) or reject the conclusion (e.g. this is not ‘coppery’ enough. This suggests that, after further testing with larger samples of copper, we might once again modify the hypothesis to something like ‘Things with a constituency of Q percent copper conduct electricity.’

How many correct predictions do we have to make to justify saying we have proven our hypothesis? In practice all we can really say is ‘A lot’. And, in practice, we need to make correct predictions in relation to the sorts of circumstances which, based on general experience, we think might affect predictive accuracy (e.g. the temperature of the copper sample, the height above sea level, the geographical and geological source of the copper, the extent and the way in which it has been prepared for the conductivity test. When a hypothesis is universal in scope, and applies to a class which is open to the future (e.g. copper that does not exist yet) as well as the past (all the copper that has ever been, most of which nobody has ever seen) we can never even say we have examined a particular percentage of the class (things made of copper). For it is certainly less than 50 percent, certainly less than 10 percent and, for all we know (because we do not know how much there is, not to mention how much, over the next few centuries, will come into being) a lot less than one percent.

How many incorrect predictions do we have to make to establish that our hypothesis is false? For many years (and some still say this) the standard answer, following Sir Karl Popper, was one. The mantra was No number of correct predictions will prove an inductively derived hypothesis to be true, but it only takes one incorrect prediction to prove a hypothesis false.

This looks reasonable. The first part is uncontroversial. That is why people prefer to speak of successful predictions as confirming a hypothesis rather than verifying the hypothesis. An accurate prediction confirms a hypothesis if, and only if, it is exactly what you would expect to happen if the hypothesis is true. That is a long way short of conclusive verification which, if the hypothesis is open-ended to the future, is an impossible dream.

So what is wrong with the (once) standard mantra? People soon realised this was not the way in which natural and social scientists behaved. At first this was dismissed, somewhat arroga论文英语论文网提供整理,提供论文代写英语论文代写代写论文代写英语论文代写留学生论文代写英文论文留学生论文代写相关核心关键词搜索。

英国英国 澳大利亚澳大利亚 美国美国 加拿大加拿大 新西兰新西兰 新加坡新加坡 香港香港 日本日本 韩国韩国 法国法国 德国德国 爱尔兰爱尔兰 瑞士瑞士 荷兰荷兰 俄罗斯俄罗斯 西班牙西班牙 马来西亚马来西亚 南非南非